Monday 8 February 2016

Notes on Heidegger's Being and Time - 2.I: Being-towards-death (pp. 274-311, §§ 45-53) - Wednesday, 3 February 2016

2.I: Dasein’s possibility of Being-a-whole, and Being-towards-death (pp. 274-311, §§ 45-53)
Wednesday, 3 February 2016 (Notes by Caroline Kaye)

Death as a consolidating concept

Placed at a strategic point of transition between the two parts of the book, between “Being” and “Time”, the section about death seems to consolidate many topics raised in the first half while preparing the way for other topics to be discussed in the second. Notwithstanding the neologisms, it is helpful to think about Dasein (thus far – what Dasein *is*) in terms of what Dasein *is not*, or its negation. A connection was made with Hegel here. The chapter signals a step into a new phase of thinking which still stresses the “ownmost” aspect of existence. Death is Dasein’s “ownmost” experience.

To whom does death belong?

One way to consider death (with being) was to consider that death belongs to those who take care of your body after physical death. There is a kind of existence (being) that carries on, but you cannot experience it as yourself. (The “deceased”) Death is something that you are aware of, but this does not extend to knowing, experiencing, *being* in death. Dasein ceases to reflect in a contemplative way when Dasein ceases to be, ceases being even.

Dying and Death

How can you not “own” something that is yours? The two experiences of birth and death are events that are Dasein’s ownmost, and yet they are not really experienced in the normal way. Everydayness lies between birth and death. No-one else can “die” on your behalf, it’s yours and yours alone, yet you still cannot experience death.

“Inauthentic being-towards-death turns away from it by merely awaiting it as a ‘someday’ eventuality. Only facing death as what it is – our ownmost, non-relational impending and not to be outstripped – is authentic”. (Steven Foulds, A Serious Guide to Being and Time)

Dasein is always my own, to reflect upon. But the reflection on cessation to exist is not what Heidegger means. He doesn’t mean our dread of dying per se, nor knowledge of the biological fact of dying.  Although that may be something a person experiences, this is not what Heidegger refers to.

“If we don’t understand our own deaths [our finitude] then we don’t understand our existence [our there-being] as persons – we lack truth, we lack certainty, and we lack conviction”. (Foulds)

It is not that we cannot reflect upon our own deaths, but that at the moment of death, the Dasein “project” is completed and reflection is no longer possible. My death is my ownmost because it defines (delimits) my life which gives it meaning.

The certainty of Death

Death is inevitable in an inductive-biological sense, but the highest level of certainty can never be achieved. The certainty of death is not the certainty of “1+1=2”, it is not an apodictic certainty. It is simply concluded by way of induction that because all people before has died, I will die myself. Since Hulme, such inductive certainty is clearly differentiated from apodictic certainty. The ‘they’ creates many methods of concealing the inevitability of death, as Foulds put it: “Death is sanitised with euphemisms, the ‘they’ provides tranquillisation about death.”

Death and authenticity

There was a discussion on the role of the supernatural, the infinite, God in Heidegger who had a strong theological background. The point was made that the notion of an afterlife emanates from a strong Christian tradition which was very dominant at the time of Heidegger’s writing (of Being and Time). We should not fall back on the notion that “if I have five years to live, I can change my life accordingly…” This is not what Heidegger means. The very idea that there is a limitation is transformative. It is the ultimate possibility, or more precisely, the very fact that makes all things count by marking Dasein’s existence as finite. For this reason, death plays a role in the creation of an authentic life.

Dasein as Being-towards-death.

Death provides Dasein with an end-point and thereby allows its existence to run a full circle and become whole. Only because Dasein is finite that its possibilities exist, otherwise whatever Dasein does would remain incidental which could be picked up or dismissed at any point during an endless existence. Only because Dasein is finite that its existence and activities matter which manifests itself in everyday life as care. The end-point of Dasein’s existence provides meaning to its existence. It is on a trajectory which points towards the end-point. Dasein is a “project” moving through time.

Death - why now?


Why didn’t Heidegger start his book with “death” or introduce the idea earlier? Having got to this part of the book, it seems now like this could have been an obvious choice on his part. Was the topic of death it deliberately avoided? Or is it an afterthought? We returned to the then prevailing discourse that Heidegger is eager to challenge. The concept of death in the first part of the book is, in a sense is “present by its absence”. (You might wonder why it isn’t mentioned as you read) Heidegger seems keen to challenge the overwhelming Christian world view that places much emphasis on a promise of life after death. In many ways, the puzzles raised by this particular chapter may not be resolved until later on in the book.



Notes on Heidegger's Being and Time - 1. VI: Care as the Being of Dasein (pp. 225-273, §§ 39-44) - Wednesday, 9 December 2015



1. VI: Care as the Being of Dasein (pp. 225-273, §§ 39-44)
Wednesday, 9 December 2015 (Notes by Marton Ribary)

Two modes of care

Care is a fundamental characteristic of Dasein’s Being-in-the world which manifests itself in two different modes. One mode is related to things drawn into Dasein’s interest what Heidegger has described as entities ready-to-hand (as opposed to things which are merely present-at-hand). The other mode is related to Others who have the same existence as Dasein itself. To simplify Heidegger’s terminological account, Dasein’s care expresses itself towards things as concern (Besorgen) and towards people as solicitude (Fürsorge).

Care, wholeness and solipsism

By bridging the chasm between Dasein and the things ready-to-hand, care expresses the wholeness of Dasein’s Being-in-the-world. It holds together the multiplicity of experiences (perceptual or otherwise) in one agent. By bridging the chasm between Dasein and Others, care avoids the philosophical threat of solipsism. It acknowledges that Dasein is not alone.

Truth and care


Heidegger maintains that truth is fundamentally the state of being “uncovered”. This manifests itself as the agreement between the statement and fact when the fundamental meaning of truth is reduced to a thing which is merely present-at-hand. Propositional truth in Heidegger’s understanding is neither general or fundamental, but a very special case of truth in the sense of being uncovered. However, like the meaning of Being, the fundamental idea of truth has been forgotten since the time of Plato and Aristotle. Heidegger interprets truth in the context of care: truth is only relevant, if it can be shared which requires that Dasein be alongside with Things ready-to hand (Besorgen) and be able to communicate it to Others (Fürsorgen).